The “matser” made world: a new conceptualization of matter and spirit
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.21847/1728-9343.2019.1(159).157444Keywords:
Cosmos-Knowing Subject, Ideas-made World, Berkeley, Matter-made World, Nkrumah, Re-Conceptualization of Matter, MatserAbstract
The world has always been, and will always be a fascinating enigma to man. Generations of thinkers have struggled to fathom the world and explain it in an intelligible formation. Till date, a thoroughly satisfactory explanation of the cosmos has not been finagled. The search for a comprehensive explanation of the world continues. Dominating the interpretations of the world are the materialistic and idealistic schools of thought. These are diametrically opposed cosmological systems without a middle ground. The materialists see the world as essentially material, devoid of any god or maker. The idealists see the world as a product of a spirit or mind. They believe the world to be fundamentally non-material in nature. Nkrumah, a thorough going materialist, believes the world to be fundamentally material in nature, Berkeley who was the most radical advocate of idealism, however, believes the world to be fundamentally spiritual. But the cosmos is, irrespective of man’s interpretation of it. It is fundamentally one in our experience. The problem lies with our conception of some phenomena as material; and some others as spiritual. How can the material and non-material interact? If the world is material, it is definitely not spiritual. If it is made of ideas only, it is definitely not material. But supposing the world is neither material nor spiritual? It could as well be that our definition of matter does not encompass some of the properties inherent in the phenomena we regard as ‘matter”. It could as well be that what we refer as “spiritual” are properties inherent in but not encompassed by the definition of what we call matter. We could as well be living in a “matserial” cosmos, a world that is fundamentally made up of substances whose properties include those we conceive as “material” and some of those we consider as “spiritual”. Perhaps it is time to re-examine our concept of matter and our concept of spirit. Perhaps, we should be talking of “matser” rather than matter and spirit. This work is a product of library research, philosophical analysis and systematic philosophical speculation. It addresses the problem of the interpretation of the world which encompasses the problem of language and the mind/matter dichotomy. It is the finding of this work that the cosmos is neither made up solely of matter or spirit. Phenomena exhibit characteristics which we traditionally describe as spiritual and material. Our conceptualizations of mind and spirit logically leads to a dual cosmos of mind and spirit, which obviously is fallacious. We are in one cosmos. The cosmos is only doubled in our language, not in our experience. Our experience of the cosmos remains one. It is the recommendation of this work that “matser” rather than mind and spirit should be used to characterize phenomena. Ours is a matserial cosmos.References
Berkeley, G. (1709). An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision. Dublin. Retrieved from https://www.maths.tcd.ie/~dwilkins/Berkeley/Vision/1709A/Vision.pdf (In English)
Berkeley, G. (1710). A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Understanding. Dublin. Retrieved from https://www.maths.tcd.ie/~dwilkins/Berkeley/HumanKnowledge/1734/HumKno.pdf (In English)
Bether, T. M. (2008). Berkeley: A Guide for the Perplexed. Continuum Publishing. London New York. (In English)
Browne, M. E. (1999). Schaum's outline of theory and problems of physics for engineering and science. Schaum's Outline Series. McGraw-Hill Companies. p. 58. (In English)
Downing, L. (2013). George Berkeley. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/berkeley/ (In English)
Gottlieb, A. (1999, July 18). God exists, philosophically (review of "Spinoza: A Life" by Steven Nadler). The New York Times. Retrieved from http://movies2.nytimes.com/books/99/07/18/reviews/990718.18gottlit.html (In English)
Bloom, H. (2006, June 16). "Deciphering Spinoza, the great original. A review of R. Goldstein. Betraying Spinoza. The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity. The New York Times. Retrieved from https://www.nytimes.com/2006/06/18/books/review/18bloom.html (In English)
Holzner, S (2005). Physics for Dummies. Wiley, John & Sons, Incorporated. p. 64. (In English)
Kant, I. (198). Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge University Press. Retrieved from http://strangebeautiful.com/other-texts/kant-first-critique-cambridge.pdf (In English)
King James Bible Version: Daniel 4.17; Genesis 1.2; Genesis 1.28; 1 Kings 8.27
McGuire, J. E. (1972). Boyle’s conception of nature. Journal of the History of Ideas, 33(4), 523-542. (In English)
Michael, P. (Ed.). (2000). Theism and Humanism. Seattle. (In English)
Nkrumah, K. (1964). Consciencism: Philosophy and Ideology for Decolonization. Retrieved from https://consciencism.files.wordpress.com/2016/12/consciencism-philosophy-and-ideology-for-de-colonisation-20161.pdf (In English)
Plato (c. 360 BC). Phaedo. Translated by Benjamin Jowett. Retrieved from http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/phaedo.html (In English)
Plato (c. 360 BC). Timaeus. Translated by Benjamin Jowett. Retrieved from https://susanwisebauer.com/story-of-science/plato-timaeus-c-360-bc/ (In English)
Russell, B. (1945). A History of Western Philosophy. Simon & Schuster. Retrieved from http://www.ntslibrary.com/PDF%20Books/History%20of%20Western%20Philosophy.pdf (In English)
Sartre, J. (1948). Existentialism and Humanism. SOLD Publisher.
Sepharial. (n.d). Second Sight: A Study of Natural and Induced Clairvoyance. United States: Library of Alexandria.
Spinoza, B. (1883). Correspondence.
Thrane & Susan. (2010). Hindu end of life death, dying, suffering, and karma. Journal of Hospice and Palliative Nursing, 12(6), 337-342. DOI: 10.1097/NJH.0b013e3181f2ff11 (in English).
Downloads
Published
How to Cite
Issue
Section
License
Copyright (c) 2019 Socrates Ebo
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.
1. Authors bear responsibility for the accuracy of facts, quotations, numbers and names used.
2. Manuscripts are not sent back.
3. The publisher does not always agree with the authors' opinion.
4. The authors reserve the right to authorship of the work and pass the first publication right of this work to the journal under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution Non-Commercial License, which allows others to freely distribute the published research with the obligatory reference to the authors of the original work and the first publication of the work in this journal.
5. The authors have the right to conclude separate supplement agreements that relate to non-exclusive work distribution in the form in which it has been published by the journal (for example, to upload the work to the online storage of the journal or publish it as part of a monograph), provided that the reference to the first publication of the work in this journal is included.