The J. Fodor's language of thought hypothesis and epistemic logic

Authors

  • Konstantin Rayhert Odessa I. I. Mechnikov National University, Ukraine

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.21847/1728-9343.2016.3(143).74853

Keywords:

language of thought hypothesis, epistemic logic, modal logic, propositional attitudes, relations

Abstract

The study is to show the similarities between J. Fodor's Language of Thought hypothesis and epistemic modal logic. According to the J. Fodor's hypothesis there is the language of thought (also called "Mentalese") that is the meta-language in which mental representations of attitudes of organism to propositions expressed in object-language (for example: knowledge, belief, hope, desire, statement) are formulated. These attitudes are called "propositional attitudes". In the hypothesis propositional attitudes are thoughts and relations between organism and proposition. Propositional attitudes are of interest for epistemic modal logics. In epistemic logics propositional attitudes are relations considered as modalities, i.e. propositions with modal operators. On certain conditions J. Fodor's Language of Thought hypothesis may be considered as a sort of epistemic modal logic, only it would require certain updating as a formal logical system. The similarities between J. Fodor's Language of Thought and epistemic modal logics give two opportunities. First opportunity is to make special version of epistemic modal logic as an instrument of research for cognitive psychology based on J. Fodor's Language of Thought hypothesis. Second opportunity is to accept the idea of J. Fodor's Language of Thought as an innate language and to attain comprehension that epistemic modal logics are not especially constructed formal languages (formal systems) but innate cognitive programs. It might enable to extrapolate the idea of innate languages onto all formal languages including logical languages and to attempt verifying that idea experimentally within cognitive sciences.

Author Biography

Konstantin Rayhert, Odessa I. I. Mechnikov National University

candidate of philosophical sciences, associate professor of the department of philosophy of natural sciences faculties

References

Bezhanishvili, M. N. (2009). Epistemic Logic. Encyclopedia of Epistemology and Philosophy of Science.Moscow: Canon+ Rehabilitation, pp. 1155-1158.

Kostyuk, V. N. (2010). Epistemic Logic. New Philosophical Encyclopedia. Vol. 4. Moscow: Mysl, 2010, pp. 450-451.

Aydede M. (2010), The Language of Thought Hypothesis, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/language-thought/.

Braddon-Mitchell, D. & Fitzpatrick, J. (1990). Explanation and the Language of Thought. Synthese. № 1 (83), pp. 3-29. doi : 10.1007/978-94-011-3716-4_2.

Cook, R. T. (2009). A Dictionary of Philosophical Logic. Edinburgh:EdinburghUniversity Press.

Dennett, D. C. (1981). Cure for the Common Code, The Language and Thought Series. Harvard University Press, рр. 64-77. doi: 10.4159/harvard.9780674594722.c6.

Dennett, D. C. (1987). Reflections: the Language of Thought Reconsidered. The Intentional Stance.Cambridge;London: MIT Press, pp. 227-235.

Fodor, J. A. (1981). Propositional Attitudes. The Language and Thought Series. Harvard University Press, рр. 45-63. doi: 10.4159/harvard.9780674594722.c5.

Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in Philosophy of Mind.Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

Fodor, J. A. (1975). The Language of Thought. N.Y.: Thomas Y. Crowell.

Fodor, J. A. & Pylyshyn Z. W. (1988). Connectionalism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis. Connections and Symbols.Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology, pp. 3-71. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(88)90031-5.

Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. Cornell:CornellUniversity Press.

Johnson, M. (2008). Philosophy’s Debt to Metaphor. The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought.Cambridge:CambridgeUniversity Press, pp. 39-52. doi: 10.1017/cbo9780511816802.004.

Johnson, M. (2007). The Meaning of the Body: Aesthetic of Human Understanding.Chicago;London:University ofChicago Press. doi: 10.7208/Chicago/9780226026992.001.0001.

Knowles, J. (1998). The Language of Thought and Natural Language Understanding. Analysis. № 4 (58), pp. 264-272. doi: 10.1093/analys/58.4.264.

Laurence, S. & Margolis, E. (1997). Regress Arguments against the Language of Thought. Analysis. Vol. 57. № 1, pp. 60-66. doi: 10.1093/analys/57.1.60.

Levine, J. (1988). Demonstrating in Mentalese. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. № 69, pp. 222-240.

Lewis, D. (1999). Reduction of Mind. Papers in metaphysics and epistemology. Cambridge University Press, рр. 291-324. doi: 10.1017/cbo9780511625343.019.

Loar, B. (1982). Must Beliefs Be Sentences? PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Vol. 2. Symposia and Invited Papers (1982).Chicago:University ofChicago Press, pp. 627-643. doi: 10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1982.2.192488.

Pinker, S. (1994). The Language Instinct. The General Psychologist, Vol. 30(3), рр. 103-105. doi: 10.1037/e412952005-009.

Rey, G. (1991). Sensations in a Language of Thought. Philosophical Issues. Vol. 1. Consciousness. 1991, pp. 73-112. doi: 10.2307/1522925.

Smith, Churchland P. & Churchland, P. M. (1983). Stalking the Wild Epistemic Engine. Nous. Vol. 17. № 1, pp. 5-18. doi: 10.2307/2214808.

von Wright, G. H. (1951). An Essay in Modal Logic. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.

Published

2016-08-01

How to Cite

Rayhert, K. (2016). The J. Fodor’s language of thought hypothesis and epistemic logic. Skhid, (3(143). https://doi.org/10.21847/1728-9343.2016.3(143).74853

Issue

Section

Philosophy